The Wealth of Nations

The Wealth of Nations

by

Adam Smith

Teachers and parents! Our Teacher Edition on The Wealth of Nations makes teaching easy.

The Wealth of Nations: Book 5, Chapter 1 Summary & Analysis

Summary
Analysis
“Part I. Of the Expence of Defence.” Every nation needs a military force to defend itself against invaders. In hunting and herding societies, everyone can take up arms together if necessary, and they do not need to be paid. Herders’ armies are larger and more formidable than hunters’, and they can even overtake powerful civilizations. In simple settled nations, where most people are farmers and there is little trade, most adult men are physically able to fight in a war. Their families must stay at home to tend their farms, but the soldiers generally do not expect compensation, so long as they are only leaving for a short campaign between planting and harvest time.
Books I–IV focused on Smith’s innovative new theory of political economy, but Book V departs from this focus somewhat in order to offer a comprehensive theory of what the government should do and how it should pay for it. Much like his detailed policy analysis of the mercantile system in Book IV, his observations in Book V are largely an attempt to convince his friends and peers in government to govern Britain differently. This chapter discusses the government’s responsibilities: defense, justice, infrastructure, secular and religious education, and administration. Smith’s analysis of defense in early societies indicates that governments need not go to great lengths to fund armies, so long as most of their people remain farmers.
Themes
Labor, Markets, and Growth Theme Icon
Institutions and Good Governance Theme Icon
Paying soldiers becomes necessary as societies progress in manufacturing and warfighting. Manufacturers and artisans work year-round and stop earning revenue if they go to fight in a war, so the sovereign has to pay them to cover the shortfall. As societies and their military technologies develop, wars become longer and more complex, and a smaller and smaller portion of the workforce can realistically become soldiers. Thus, while all men learned basic military skills and were prepared for battle in ancient Greece and Rome, modern societies require a specialized class of soldiers. The state must pay these soldiers to make military service worth their while.
The division of labor affects the military just like it does any other sector of the economy: soldiers become specialized professionals who earn wages for their work. Instead of everyone performing military service for short periods of time when circumstances demand, a smaller number of people become soldiers, but they serve for longer. Unlike in farming or manufacturing, efficiency gains in fighting aren’t necessarily a good thing—rather, this can make war longer, more widespread, and more destructive than before.
Themes
Labor, Markets, and Growth Theme Icon
Institutions and Good Governance Theme Icon
As society advances and the division of labor progresses, people spend less and less time on military exercise, so the state has two options: form a militia by requiring everyone to perform military service, or form a standing army by permanently hiring a smaller group of professional soldiers. Over time, militias have become more organized. Firearms have made physical training less important, but skill, discipline, and morale more important. Standing armies are better at all three, so they are superior to militias in most cases.
Since it makes little sense for citizens to pay soldiers directly for their service, the military becomes a branch of government. The state’s choices about how to structure it start to matter greatly, both financially and militarily. Militias may cost less and enable citizens to defend themselves if the nation faces invasion, but a standing army’s dedication and specialized training makes it superior. This is why nearly all countries have standing armies today.
Themes
Institutions and Good Governance Theme Icon
The Arabs and Turks have the best militias, since they obey the same leaders in peacetime and war. And once a militia spends long enough in the field, it acquires the same level of training as a standing army. The American Revolution started less than a year ago, and the militia leading it may soon reach this point. Otherwise, standing armies historically defeat militias. For instance, Macedon defeated other Greek republics and then the Persian Empire.
Militias can rise to the level of standing armies in some instances, but Smith’s analysis suggests that they face a significant disadvantage in the early part of a war. Yet his predictions about the American Revolution were remarkably accurate, and they show that an army or militia’s level of skill, discipline, and morale can vary widely depending on the circumstances. For instance, the American militiamen stood to gain far more from winning the war than Britain’s soldiers did from losing it, which certainly affected morale.
Themes
Institutions and Good Governance Theme Icon
Get the entire The Wealth of Nations LitChart as a printable PDF.
The Wealth of Nations PDF
The history of the Roman army also illustrates this point. Carthage won many victories over Rome, until the Roman militia trained enough to become a standing army. This Roman army then soundly defeated Carthage and went on to dominate the region for centuries. After Rome conquered the whole Mediterranean, it stopped sending its soldiers to war and started stationing them throughout the Empire instead. They turned back into merchants and tradesmen, and so the standing army once again became a disorganized militia. This is how the German and Scythian tribal militias were able to overthrow the Empire. Indeed, militias in shepherding nations are generally stronger than militias in civilized nations. After the Empire fell and peacetime resumed, the militiamen became tradesmen and merchants, then fell out of practice and were replaced by standing armies.
The Punic Wars again show how an untrained militia can turn a war around after a series of early defeats, but the sacking of Rome shows how military success led to complacency and undermined military readiness. But if Rome had kept a standing army of trained soldiers instead of a militia, it may have successfully defended itself. Indeed, this is similar to the logic of competition and monopoly: competitive firms are the best-run and most efficient, while firms with monopolies grow complacent and inefficient. Herding nations’ militias are stronger for the same reasons Smith outlined above: they tend to obey the same leaders in peace and war, and they generally spend significant amounts of time fighting, so gain training equivalent to a standing army’s.
Themes
Institutions and Good Governance Theme Icon
Civilized countries thus need standing armies to defend themselves because only a standing army remains practiced and brave enough in peacetime to defeat invading militias. In turn, establishing a standing army is the best way to impose discipline and civilization on a country. It’s true that standing armies sometimes overthrow governments instead of supporting them, but this won’t happen if the same people lead both. Put differently, the sovereign should command the army. This also keeps the sovereign’s power secure, which in turn protects people: the sovereign can tolerate dissent, instead of needing to crush it to keep a hold on power.
Even if militias can sometimes outmatch standing armies, they are no substitute for a nation that wants to be sure of its ability to defend itself. After all, capital owners need a guarantee of security in order to be sure that they will see the returns from their investments. Smith’s vision of a disciplined standing army controlled by the sovereign, which can deter revolutions rather than launching them or having to suppress dissent to prevent them, is fundamental to most modern democracies.
Themes
Institutions and Good Governance Theme Icon
In short, defense grows more complex and more expensive as society develops. Firearms accelerated this shift, and the ability to buy and produce them is now the most important factor in warfighting. This gives rich nations a consistent advantage over poor nations for the first time, which civilizes everyone.
Not only do the military’s gains from specialization follow the same logic as economic development in general, but with the rise of advanced military technology, economic development also determines who wins wars. Smith sees the domination of the poor by the rich as a civilizing influence, because it can prevent random violence and spread the institutions that make rich countries rich, but his analysis of colonialism also suggests that these same factors can encourage oppressive monopolies.
Themes
Labor, Markets, and Growth Theme Icon
Institutions and Good Governance Theme Icon
“Part II. Of the Expence of Justice.” In primitive societies, where people own little property, there is no need for a formal justice system. Unlike property crime, violent crime in no way benefits the perpetrator, so most people refrain from it. But once people have property, they start to steal it from each other and need a justice system to govern it. People have to submit to that justice system in order for it to function. People usually subordinate themselves to people who have qualifications, are elders, control money and resources, or belong to a hereditary nobility or monarchy. Hunters don’t have wealth and hereditary distinctions, while herders have them more than any other kind of group. These distinctions lead herders to form governments, as people with property seek to protect it against people without it.
The justice system develops as the division of labor progresses, much like the military (and every branch of the economy). Specifically, it depends on the accumulation of capital, the same development that makes investment and economic growth possible, but also brings about economic inequality. Hunters’ livelihood is organized around labor, while herders’ depends on property (their livestock), so it’s little surprise that herders have more unequal societies with more robust systems of justice. But these justice systems still do not need to be professionalized, with lawyers and justices in charge. Rather, the existing social hierarchy simply resolves disputes, in addition to governing society.
Themes
Labor, Markets, and Growth Theme Icon
Institutions and Good Governance Theme Icon
By forcing lawbreakers to pay, sovereigns turn justice systems into a source of revenue. Indeed, judges in Britain were once little more than traveling tax collectors. They were corrupt, slow, and accountable to no-one. In many herding tribes, the sovereign is simply the wealthiest herdsman, and their revenue comes from gifts people offer them in exchange for protection, so they have no incentive to stop corruption.
Judges have a strong incentive to abuse their power, which blurs the line between justice and corruption. In fact, the herding tribes’ system may be the  epitome of corruption, as it combines political, economic, and juridical power in one person’s hands. The solution to this corruption is clearly to separate judicial fees from judges’ earnings.
Themes
Institutions and Good Governance Theme Icon
But in societies that collect taxes, judges are paid salaries and not allowed to accept gifts. Judges are not particularly costly to the government, in part because the position is honorable enough that people take it for little pay. But there is nothing wrong with charging court fees to cover this cost, so long as those fees are charged fairly.
As Smith noted in Book I, honor is one of the factors that can reduce a job’s salary, since people are willing to do prestigious work for less than the market value of their labor. This is still common today: in many countries, wages are significantly lower in the public sector than the private sector, but public sector jobs are still prized.
Themes
Labor, Markets, and Growth Theme Icon
Institutions and Good Governance Theme Icon
If judges are paid for their diligence in making decisions, as in France, they may act slower but will never be corrupt. In contrast, England’s courts earned more fees the more cases they tried, so they became quicker but took on many more cases. Courts paid per proceeding would simply multiply the proceedings, just as attorneys paid by the page tend to “multiply words beyond all necessity” in their work. Endowing courts with properties or investments is one good solution for covering their costs.
Both the English and French systems are less than ideal, as tying pay to any kind of performance metric simply incentivizes people to maximize that metric (while their actual performance suffers). Even today, lawyers still go to great lengths to maximize their billable hours. But on the other hand, simply paying legal professionals a flat salary risks removing any incentive for them to do their best work.
Themes
Institutions and Good Governance Theme Icon
As societies become more complex, sovereigns appoint deputies to make judicial decisions. In the same way, governments develop specialized executive and judicial branches, which should be separate and independent so that judges can make impartial decisions free from political influence.
The separation of powers is based on the same principle as the division of labor, applied to government. The more that different people can specialize in different governing functions, the more effective they—and the overall system—are likely to become.
Themes
Labor, Markets, and Growth Theme Icon
Institutions and Good Governance Theme Icon
“Part III. Of the Expence of public Works and public Institutions.” The sovereign’s third duty, after defense and justice, is creating the other crucial institutions that would never return a profit to private investors. Specifically, these are the institutions necessary for commerce, the education of the youth, and the religious instruction of all people. The three Articles in this section will cover these three topics.
The bulk of this chapter will focus on infrastructure, state-chartered corporations, schools, and churches. While these may often be privately-run today, Smith sees them as essential public services that the government must provide, both to support the economy and to ensure that citizens live dignified lives. 
Themes
Institutions and Good Governance Theme Icon
“Article I. Of the public Works and Institutions for facilitating the Commerce of Society. And, first, of those which are necessary for facilitating Commerce in general.” The wealthier a country, the better infrastructure and public services it needs to perform large-scale manufacturing and trade. Since these projects are investments that pay for themselves, they shouldn’t be counted as expenses from the government’s general revenue. Instead, they should form a separate fund and be managed in a way that raises revenue for the government while facilitating the transport and exchange of goods.
Major projects like roads, bridges, ports, and now airports and transit systems greatly reduce the cost of doing business. No country can grow economically powerful without this kind of infrastructure—although it’s no coincidence that major commercial centers like London are generally port cities that require less of it. Smith’s point about classifying infrastructure projects separately from the general revenue may seem like a minor accounting issue, but it’s actually crucial. It means that infrastructure investment actually pays off for the government in the long term, so as long as it can afford the initial capital expenditure, it should practically always pursue them. Many of the other people who live at the government’s expense (like soldiers and judges) are unproductive laborers, but the people who build infrastructure are among the most productive laborers in the whole economy.
Themes
Labor, Markets, and Growth Theme Icon
Capital Accumulation and Investment Theme Icon
Institutions and Good Governance Theme Icon
For instance, tolls can pay for roads and bridges, seigniorage can more than cover the cost of minting coinage, and post offices usually generate more revenue than they incur in costs. These services make doing business so much cheaper that taxing them to repay their cost of construction will not deter people from using them. Commercial tolls should be proportional to the weight and size of goods transported, and people’s willingness to pay tolls will determine which projects are worth building. In turn, this ensures that projects are built in the right places, where people most need them.
Smith continues to lay out specific policy proposals that he hopes Britain can use to govern more wisely. He once again implies that Britain is foolish not to charge seigniorage, and he proposes proportional tolls so as not to disadvantage smaller shipments. After all, merchants could game the system otherwise, for instance by transporting all their goods together in particularly large shipments to save on toll costs (and deprive the government on revenue). The same principle applies to shipping mail through the post office. Still, Smith’s principle that public services should be publicly owned remains controversial—for instance, Britain privatized its postal service in 2013.
Themes
Institutions and Good Governance Theme Icon
Canals should be privately owned because governments cannot keep up with the constant maintenance they need to be navigable. Roads should be publicly run because roads do not need constant maintenance to be drivable, so private companies would be incentivized to charge the highest possible tolls but keep roads in the worst possible condition.
Each kind of infrastructure project has its own particular requirements, and advancements in technology have significantly changed them. But the principle behind Smith’s analysis is still clear and relevant: the closer the correlation between what yields profit and what benefits the public, the more reasonable private ownership becomes. Canals cannot function without a profit motive, but roads cannot function with it.
Themes
Institutions and Good Governance Theme Icon
People complain about Britain’s poorly-managed public turnpike system, but it needs time to develop best practices. The government should not raise the tolls as high as possible to raise revenue, as has been proposed. This would discourage commerce, harm the poor, and encourage bad maintenance. In France, roads are managed publicly, and everyone is required to work a few days a year maintaining them. France’s main roads are better than Britain’s, but its country roads are dangerous and impassable. It is said that China’s publicly managed roads and canals are excellent. Local governments should maintain and raise the taxes to pay for local infrastructure. They are sometimes corrupt, but much less so than the central government.
The comparison among Britain, France, and China is a clear example of how different governance systems shape the quality of infrastructure—and, in turn, the ease of doing business. Smith’s proposals for Britain’s roads show that facilitating commerce is more important than maximizing tax revenue. After all, the growth in trade will generate extra revenue in its own right. And his proposal to let local governments oversee roads once again suggests that infrastructure ought to be managed by the people who have the greatest, most direct economic incentives to keep it in good working order for the public.
Themes
Institutions and Good Governance Theme Icon
Mercantilism and Free Trade Theme Icon
“Of the Public Works and Institutions which are necessary for facilitating particular Branches of Commerce.” Trade with other parts of the world often requires building forts and hiring ambassadors, and it’s not unreasonable to pay for them by taxing those who participate in this trade. But European countries have wrongly let companies administer those taxes instead of the executive.
Readers already know that Smith supports a competitive system of private enterprise in most sectors of the economy, but international trade involves many special considerations that justify some level of government involvement. In this section, Smith will explain how European governments have privatized the dimensions of international trade that should be public (like tax collection), while giving monopolies to publicly-chartered companies in the areas of trade that should be private. Even if trading nations may no longer build forts or charter exclusive companies, Smith’s commentary is still relevant. After all, ambassadors and trade associations are still important today.
Themes
Labor, Markets, and Growth Theme Icon
Institutions and Good Governance Theme Icon
Mercantilism and Free Trade Theme Icon
There are two kinds of companies: regulated and joint-stock companies. Regulated companies control a certain branch of trade and allow any merchant to join for a fee. When these companies are powerful, they restrict the trade and create pointless regulations. It’s far better when they’re weak, because that just makes them useless, like the Hamburgh, Russia, and Eastland Companies. The Turkey Company imposes a repressive company monopoly on Britain’s trade with Turkey, which discourages people from joining it. These regulated companies have not generally maintained forts, and they aren’t suited for doing so, since their managers don't have a personal stake in their success or substantial resources to invest. Britain’s other regulated company, the Royal African Company, is supposed to maintain forts, but it instead behaves monopolistically and wastes its budget.
Regulated companies are similar to the corporations (or guilds) that Smith decried in Book I. Merchants must pay to join them if they want to participate in a certain branch of international trade. And if they did maintain forts to protect British merchants and their cargo, Smith suggests, maybe they would be viable. But instead of facilitating commerce, these companies just act as monopolies to various degrees. Smith clearly thinks that they should be dismantled, so that merchants can trade freely. Moreover, by comparing them side-by-side, Smith points out that one company’s loss is another’s gain. For instance, the Turkey Company’s monopoly makes trading with Turkey undesirable, so merchants are likely to put their capital into trading with other countries instead.
Themes
Institutions and Good Governance Theme Icon
Mercantilism and Free Trade Theme Icon
In joint-stock companies, people pool their resources and become co-owners. These joint-stock companies are not the same as private partnerships: stock owners can sell their shares to anyone and have more limited liability. These conditions attract incompetent investors and boards of directors.
The publicly traded joint-stock company was a relatively new invention in Smith’s time. He had no way of knowing that it would become the dominant structure for businesses in the centuries after his death, or that the concept of limited corporate liability would become so widely accepted as to be taken for granted throughout the world. Of course, none of this invalidates Smith’s critique of limited liability—which many contemporary legal scholars share.
Themes
Institutions and Good Governance Theme Icon
Some companies have exclusive trade privileges, while others have lost theirs—like the Royal African Company, which failed as a result. The Hudson’s Bay Company has succeeded because it has no real competitors and very few stockowners, who make low but respectable profits. The South Sea Company bankrupted itself enslaving and selling people to Spain, then whaling in Greenland.
The Royal African Company’s monopoly was specifically for the slave trade—in fact, it was most likely the largest slave-trading institution in human history. Smith only addresses this in passing, but contemporary readers should pause to consider the implications of his analysis. Today, we often assume that Europeans enslaved Africans because this was cheaper for them, and the slave trade was profitable. But actually, the Royal African and South Sea Companies went bankrupt. In other words, Smith suggests that the transatlantic slave trade was not just inhumane but also a disastrous business mistake that didn’t even benefit the enslavers.
Themes
Institutions and Good Governance Theme Icon
Mercantilism and Free Trade Theme Icon
The first East India Company failed due to competition, but Parliament allowed it to continue trading with some of its capital until 1701. Its officials also kept privately trading goods, and their competition made the second East India Company lose money—until it amassed an army and started conquering territory in India, giving it a company monopoly. It keeps demanding higher dividends and financial relief from the government. It is poorly managed because its members and directors care about their immediate profits, and not the company, the Empire, or India.
The East India Company is only staying afloat because it has seized land and resources by force. Its profit comes from plunder, not productive trade. Smith’s analysis of the East India Company is also interesting in historical perspective. He was writing at the very beginning of more than a century of Company rule in India, which only came to an end when Indian soldiers in the Company’s army mutinied against its extreme cruelty and poor governance. The crown was forced to take India over, in an attempt to clean up the Company’s proverbial mess. In this way, Smith encourages us to rethink the commonsense distinction between private corporations and public institutions. The East India Company’s history shows how the corporate system privatizes the gains from commerce, while forcing the public to bear the costs.
Themes
Labor, Markets, and Growth Theme Icon
Institutions and Good Governance Theme Icon
Mercantilism and Free Trade Theme Icon
Quotes
Joint-stock companies tend to encourage waste and corruption, start unjust wars, and fail unless they have monopolies (which are justifiable when necessary to create a new branch of trade, but foolish when granted in perpetuity). Fifty-five joint-stock companies with exclusive trade privileges have failed, too. Joint-stock companies without these privileges can only succeed in banking, insurance, and canal and aqueduct construction. There are two reasons for this. First, these are methodical, rule-based industries where management quality is unimportant. Second, their work requires massive capital investment but greatly benefits the public. No other industry meets these requirements.
Smith sees the majority of joint-stock companies as mismanaged disasters, in large part because of the concept of limited liability.. This is yet another reminder that, even if Smith’s analysis of free and competitive markets is the foundation for how experts think about the economy today, this doesn’t mean he would favor expanding corporate power or agree with the way our economic institutions are run today. He only supports joint-stock companies in banking, insurance, canals, and aqueducts because he sees any other corporate structure as unlikely to raise the requisite amount of capital.
Themes
Labor, Markets, and Growth Theme Icon
Capital Accumulation and Investment Theme Icon
Institutions and Good Governance Theme Icon
Mercantilism and Free Trade Theme Icon
Money and Banking Theme Icon
“Article II. Of the Expence of the Institutions for the Education of Youth.” Schools can be paid for either through fees or an endowment, although endowments reduce the quality of instruction by removing an incentive for good teaching. University members do as little work as they can get away with—and all the university can make them do is give lectures. Students often choose a university for its degrees or scholarships, rather than the quality of its teaching. Reasonable teachers don’t want students to hate their lectures, so do the bare minimum to please them, like by just reading through books in class and making unoriginal, uncontroversial remarks. Since university students are adults, universities would not have to discipline them if classes were really worth attending.
Smith spent his whole career as a scholar and professor, so his remarks on education are grounded in his personal experiences and frustrations. For instance, he famously complained that the teaching at Oxford was far worse than at the much poorer University of Glasgow because Oxford’s wealth and fame made its professors complacent. This is part of why he supports tying teachers’ compensation as directly as possible to their performance. That system would make education more competitive, reward the best teachers, and better serve students. Unlike in many of the other sectors that Smith covers, university administration has not unified around a single model. For instance, American universities are more likely to have endowments today, while German ones generally depend on annual public funding.
Themes
Labor, Markets, and Growth Theme Icon
Capital Accumulation and Investment Theme Icon
Institutions and Good Governance Theme Icon
Private schools are more efficient than public ones because they’re funded by student fees, so their revenue depends on their performance. But universities specialize at subjects that would not be profitable to teach privately. They started as religious institutions, so they required students to learn Latin. They have incorporated more and more Greek for the study of philosophy, which historically has three branches: physics, ethics, and logic. Religious education added two more branches, metaphysics and ontology, which were largely a waste of time. It also corrupted ethics by refocusing it on an afterlife. But this curriculum is still the standard in universities, and most useful philosophical work is happening outside them.
Even as he praises universities for teaching important but impractical knowledge, Smith is remarkably critical of his own profession. Indeed, his analysis of university philosophy curricula reveals his professional biases. Contemporary readers may be surprised to see him argue that the most significant philosophical research was happening outside of universities, since today virtually all philosophy happens within them. But Smith suggests that his contemporary universities merely repeat what philosophers thought in the past, without actually teaching students to think philosophically.
Themes
Institutions and Good Governance Theme Icon
Wealthy families are foolish to send their sons to universities only fit for the clergy, instead of schools where they can learn to do what their professions will actually demand. More and more young English people go traveling abroad instead of attending university, which is even worse. It wastes their time and makes them undisciplined.
Smith’s call for practical rather than liberal education may seem strange, but his point is that universities don’t truly provide a liberal education either. And his disdain for wealthy young people’s Grand Tours around Europe is curious, because he spent three years taking his young patron on such a tour before starting to write this book.
Themes
Institutions and Good Governance Theme Icon
In ancient Greece, citizens generally received public education in music and gymnastics. They just learned gymnastics in ancient Rome—but music was unnecessary, as it’s an uncivilized art form. While the instructors in these subjects were volunteers, private tutors taught others: reading, writing, and arithmetic. Philosophy was taught in private schools in Greece. Philosophers traveled and lectured for fees, until they made enough money to establish such schools. Their students received neither degrees nor practical expertise. Similarly, many wealthy Romans privately studied law. They were the first to treat law as a systematic science and expect judges to take oaths and issue prudent, defensible, and public decisions.
Putting aside Smith’s prejudices against music, he clearly thinks that Greece and Rome offered citizens a better education than modern England because they treated it like a competitive market. This enabled the best teachers to rise to the top, reach more students, and spread their ideas. The best ideas would thus spread the furthest. Smith also points out how, unlike modern education, ancient education taught critical thinking and drew clear connections between theory and practice. There is little doubt that curricula have moved back in this direction since he was writing in the 18th century.
Themes
Labor, Markets, and Growth Theme Icon
Institutions and Good Governance Theme Icon
Overall, the principle of competition made education better in the ancient world than in Smith’s time, when public university teaching is the worst job for a scholar. Unlike public university teachers, private tutors can only make a living teaching things that are actually useful. Women’s education is better than men’s because it is entirely private and well suited to their role in society.
Like so many of Smith’s other observations, these comments clearly no longer apply to the present day, when professorships are coveted and education is no longer gender-segregated. But again, the basic principles behind his argument still make sense. Namely, the more practical, specialized, and personalized the education, the closer relationship there is between the quality of that education and students’ life outcomes. Accordingly, teaching will be more competitive and superior in quality.
Themes
Labor, Markets, and Growth Theme Icon
The more the division of labor advances, the more the state needs to educate the public. This is because most people with specialized jobs only perform “a few very simple operations,” so the masses in advanced societies quickly learn everything they need to know at work and become “stupid and ignorant” about everything else. In hunting, herding, and simpler farming societies, most people become well-rounded and refined—they develop good judgment because they constantly have to resolve many different kinds of problems.
Readers may be shocked to hear Smith argue that the division of labor, which he has consistently praised throughout this whole work, actually makes people “stupid and ignorant.” Only universal public education can ensure that specialized workers know about the world outside their narrow area of focus. And humanistically-minded readers may ask whether a wealthy society full of “stupid and ignorant” people is truly preferable to a poorer but wiser one. Indeed, critics of capitalism have long seized on this point as a key issue with building society around the division of labor.
Themes
Labor, Markets, and Growth Theme Icon
Institutions and Good Governance Theme Icon
Quotes
In advanced societies, the division of labor means that a few people can spend all of their time on contemplation. If they are given the right positions, these people can greatly help society, but if not, their superior knowledge gets wasted. Wealthy and noble families can spend handsomely to give their children an extensive private education, but most people have to work as soon as they are old enough, so they never have time for education. It is inexpensive and very beneficial for the state to teach everybody reading, writing, and arithmetic in public schools at a young age. This system is succeeding in Scotland and England. Offering prizes for high achievers and technical examinations for tradespeople would encourage it to improve.
The division of labor may make most people “stupid and ignorant,” but it gives a select few the opportunity to specialize in acquiring knowledge and using it for the public good. These people, of course, are philosophers. (In Smith’s time, philosophy comprised much more than it does today—including most of the disciplines now taught in the modern university.) Unfortunately, access to intellectual life depended on social class, but society could move marginally towards educational equality by providing public education to all—and additional opportunities for the most capable youth.
Themes
Labor, Markets, and Growth Theme Icon
Institutions and Good Governance Theme Icon
The Greeks and Romans encouraged physical excellence through gymnastics training and prizes. By following this example, nations could reduce the size of their standing armies and their expenditures on defense. They could prevent their people from becoming cowardly, which makes them useless and unhappy. So do ignorance and stupidity, which lead the populace to disrespect their leaders and fail to understand policies that oppress them.
At the beginning of this chapter, Smith outlined the difference between a militia and a (more effective) standing army. Here, he proposes building training into the education system in order to have both: a larger citizens’ militia to supplement a smaller, specialized army. His comments about stupidity and ignorance indicate that public education also helps people make better collective decisions and keep the government accountable.
Themes
Institutions and Good Governance Theme Icon
“Article III. Of the Expence of the Institutions for the Instruction of People of all Ages.” Religious teachings serve people of all ages, and private religion teachers are more zealous and hardworking than established clergy paid from endowments, as they earn revenue directly from their followers. This helps explain why new religious movements develop fast. Similarly, low-level Roman  Catholic clergy live from parishioners’ charity, so they have strong reasons to serve the people.
Some countries (including the UK) still have a state religion and government-supported churches, but the vast majority of the world’s population now lives in legally secular states. But even if religion is no longer the state’s responsibility and religious education has grown less important in many places, Smith’s discussion of it can still help us understand why some organized religions are growing today (and others are shrinking). As with schools, he analyzes religions as a competitive market, with their success largely depending on how closely they connect with their followers’ lives.
Themes
Labor, Markets, and Growth Theme Icon
Institutions and Good Governance Theme Icon
Philosopher David Hume distinguishes between the majority of professions, which people freely join for the rewards and compensation they provide, and a few professions that the state ought to regulate and promote, either to make them attractive or to make them support society’s best interests. The clergy may appear to be the first kind, but it’s actually the second, as a predictable religious establishment is preferable to an industry of zealous, self-interested preachers who distort the truth, inflame passions, and challenge the established social order in order to grow their following.
David Hume was a close friend of Adam Smith’s and arguably the central figure of the Scottish Enlightenment. Like many other philosophers throughout history, he recognized religion’s great moral, social, and emotional power over people—and argued that a healthy society needed to use that power for good rather than evil. His distinction between intrinsically valuable and state-regulated professions is really just the distinction between work that serves private and public interests.
Themes
Labor, Markets, and Growth Theme Icon
Institutions and Good Governance Theme Icon
But historically, religious establishments actually form because different religious sects align with different political factions, and the winning factions reward their allied sects with power. Religious conflict is most dangerous when two or three large sects are competing for power. In contrast, if religion never got involved in politics, many small sects would compete peacefully for customers (like merchants do).
On Hume and Smith’s view, religion’s power is never truly politically independent. Even when religious sects don’t fight for power, receive money from the government, or take specific political stances, their influence always depends on the ruling political institutions. And when they do get involved in government, they can easily sow conflict. These are all good reasons to regulate them.
Themes
Institutions and Good Governance Theme Icon
There are two approaches to morality, an austere system and a liberal system. Common people generally follow strict ideas about morality and avoid sinful indulgences. But “people of fashion” are looser and more disposed to vice, since they can usually afford to be lazy and irresponsible without wasting their fortunes. Most religious sects start with the austere system of morality and rigorously enforce proper behavior in their followers. To make sure these sects don’t go too far, the state should require all professionals to study science and philosophy, and it should support public festivals and art performances in order to give ordinary people an alternative source of entertainment (and potential zealots an alternative source of income).
People still commonly view elites as sinful, decadent, greedy, and out of touch. Smith chalks this up to economic class divisions—and specifically the distinction between living off capital or land and living off wages. Education and entertainment for the public can help bridge this gap, but it’s not clear to Smith if the people will eventually get tired of their rulers’ lavish lifestyles and overthrow them. While this wasn’t quite what was happening in the American colonies, it would occur forcefully a decade later in France, during the French Revolution. Turning zealots into entertainers is a way to make them support broader social goals instead of challenging them.
Themes
Institutions and Good Governance Theme Icon
In countries with no established religion, the sovereign does not have to work with religious leaders. But where there is one, kings must work with clergy. The church’s main interest is to maintain its power—which is based on its religious teachings. The state loses popular support if it challenges these teachings or turns against rebellious clergymen. Indeed, people are naturally stubborn, so the state should win them over with persuasion, not violence. This is doubly true for clergymen, who elect their own leaders and answer to the Pope, not the sovereign.
Even if their ultimate goals and interests differ, Smith suggests that the church and the state both benefit greatly from remaining unified. If economic elites join them, they can typically form a stable ruling class for generations. But effective government requires achieving this kind of stability, without the corruption that so often accompanies it. While there’s no concept of democracy anywhere in Smith’s work, his argument for persuasion over violence shows that he does see the consent of the governed as crucial to the state’s legitimacy.
Themes
Institutions and Good Governance Theme Icon
The clergy used to act like a landed nobility across Europe. It served the Pope like a “spiritual army” and collected rent in the form of tithes, which made it wealthy. It spent its surplus supporting the poor and currying favor with the nobility. Combined with its moral authority, this made the church so powerful that not even kings could defy it. The law didn’t apply to the church in the ancient world, and the Church of Rome governed with an iron fist during the Middle Ages. Even if people could see through its superstitions, “the ties of private interest” kept it in power.
In many respects, the church’s traditional structure resembles the feudal system. It simply collected rents without doing any work, and it consumed or hoarded its surplus instead of investing it in economic improvements. For most of Europe’s history, the church was the most powerful institution throughout the continent because it was the only one with a foothold in virtually every community. As compared with the weak, absent, or indifferent monarchs who ruled in theory, the church was the state.
Themes
Capital Accumulation and Investment Theme Icon
Institutions and Good Governance Theme Icon
The clergy’s power declined for the same reasons as the landed nobility’s did. Namely, advances in manufacturing and commerce enabled clergymen to spend their surplus on goods for themselves, instead of generosity to others. To increase this surplus, the clergy started renting its land to farmers—who started making incomes of their own, became independent, and turned against the increasingly vain, wasteful clergy. Sovereigns took the opportunity to restrict the church’s power, especially in England and France. Zealous new religious leaders launched the Protestant Reformation: they gained a following by turning against the church establishment, and some leaders and city-states throughout Europe even aligned with them (although many did not).
Smith encourages his readers to view the Protestant Revolution in historical perspective, as part of the broader process of social transformation that brought the Middle Ages to a close. The feudal system and the church’s power declined in lockstep, as the division of labor made it possible to trade with or invest an agricultural surplus (instead of just hoarding or consuming it). This encouraged clergymen to squeeze the greatest possible surplus out of their property, which in turn enabled agricultural improvements to drive further growth. In many cases, the clergy’s tactics backfired, and citizens took the opportunity to seize more political and economic power for themselves. Today, many historians see the city-states that formed during the Reformation as the first true democracies in Europe since antiquity.
Themes
Labor, Markets, and Growth Theme Icon
Capital Accumulation and Investment Theme Icon
Institutions and Good Governance Theme Icon
The reformers had no central authority, so they fought endlessly about the church’s proper structure and role in society. On one side, the Lutherans and the Church of England maintained church hierarchies and worked closely with the state. In this way, they promoted stability but fell out of touch with ordinary people.
Due to the Protestant Reformation, different European countries took different approaches to political and economic management. The Lutherans and Church of England adopted a structure reminiscent of the Catholic Church from which they broke away.
Themes
Institutions and Good Governance Theme Icon
On the other side, the Calvinists (or Presbyterians) believed that people should choose their own pastors and all clergy should have equal power and income. The election of pastors led to conflict and disorder, as clergymen tried to stand out and win support by growing more radical. Public officials started appointing them instead. Yet due to their equal status and humble pay, Calvinist clergymen are “learned, decent, independent, and respectable.” The common people actually trust and follow them. In Calvinist countries, the best scholars take university teaching jobs, but in countries where churches are more powerful than universities, they tend to become clergymen. It is better for them to teach, because this refines their knowledge and helps educate the public.
Competition may benefit the economy as a whole by rewarding the most successful firms, but it’s undesirable within the church, whose power depends on its unity. Still, the Calvinists’ humility and dependence on the people for their power made them more effective religious leaders. They had to actually provide a valuable service, because they lacked strong institutional backing. Smith’s point about university versus church employment reflects this: as the best scholars go to whichever institution treats them the best, society benefits greatly from having a stronger university system than church system. Indeed, the Reformation’s success in Scotland partly explains why the Scottish university system was so successful—and produced so many significant intellectuals like Smith.
Themes
Institutions and Good Governance Theme Icon
The church’s revenues are really part of the state’s, since it depends on tithes (which are really land taxes). But the more of this tax goes to the church, the less goes to the government, including the national defense. This means that, wherever the church is richer, the sovereign is poorer, and the people are less protected. In Switzerland, these tithes cover the full cost of running both the church and the government, and in Scotland, the church covers its expenses and serves the public on a very meager budget. Indeed, if they are overpaid, clergymen waste their time “in festivity, in vanity, and in dissipation” instead of performing their duties for the common people.
Even if some of the church’s activities benefit the public, it still mostly just enriches itself at the public’s expense. Tithes mean that people essentially have to pay rent twice, once to landlords and once to the clergy. They keep less of their own revenue, so it becomes harder for them to build wealth (and accumulate the capital that they must invest for the economy to grow). Smith will explore the consequences of taxation much more in the next chapter, but suffice it to say that the less the government and church spend in order to provide essential services, the better it is for the population. For instance, if tithes cover all government expenses in Switzerland, then there is no need for additional taxation—and the people can keep more of their income.
Themes
Capital Accumulation and Investment Theme Icon
Institutions and Good Governance Theme Icon
“Part IV. Of the Expence of Supporting the Dignity of the Sovereign.” Political leaders need homes, furniture, food, and clothing, just like everyone else. They must keep up with the upper classes in their nation, lest they lose respect, so their expenses increase the wealthier their nation gets. This effect is stronger in monarchies, whose leaders live luxuriously in order to justify the greater distance between them and ordinary citizens.
In economic terms, political leaders are unproductive laborers. Their work doesn’t yield a direct revenue, and so the state has to cover their expenses. They maintain close relationships with other social elites not just out of vanity, but because they depend on that class’s approval in order to stay in power and govern. Inequality makes this even more extreme, and it’s not uncommon for monarchs to ruin their national economies by living well beyond their means, just because nobody can stop them.
Themes
Institutions and Good Governance Theme Icon
“Conclusion.” Expenses for defense and supporting the sovereign’s dignity should come from a nation’s general revenue, because they benefit everyone. But separate court fees should pay for the justice system, and local revenue should pay for public works that primarily benefit a certain area. The general revenue can pay for roads (but tolls are preferable), just as it can pay for schools and religious education (but fees and donations are preferable). And the general revenue should pay for the institutions and public works that benefit all of society.
Smith concludes by briefly returning to each of the activities he thinks the government should perform, as well as breaking down how it should structure its accounts. In each case, he argues that the population who benefits from a public good should be the one who pays for it. This is why everyone should share the cost of defense and administration, but only the people who use roads and educational institutions should have to pay for them. Of course, modern nations have dealt with these challenges in a variety of ways, with some developing much larger centrally-funded public sectors than others.
Themes
Institutions and Good Governance Theme Icon