Utilitarianism

by

John Stuart Mill

Meta-Ethics Theme Analysis

Themes and Colors
Utilitarianism, Happiness, and The Good Life Theme Icon
Criticism and the Principles of Utility Theme Icon
The Common Good Theme Icon
Meta-Ethics Theme Icon
LitCharts assigns a color and icon to each theme in Utilitarianism, which you can use to track the themes throughout the work.
Meta-Ethics Theme Icon

How do we determine what is right and wrong? In ethics, this question, which defines the field known as meta-ethics, is as important as practical questions of which moral stances, courses of action, and social structures are actually the right and wrong ones. Like any philosopher building an ethical theory from the ground up, John Stuart Mill must offer some explanation of this: what makes happiness the best thing for humans, and therefore proves the utilitarian theory true? In Utilitarianism, he offers an unconventional answer to this question, which allows him to circumvent and undercut all these meta-ethical debates entirely: he says that happiness is desirable simply because “people do actually desire it,” and that this fact is impossible to deny or refute.

By looking at previous philosophers’ work and reflecting on the role of ethics in human life, Mill identifies meta-ethical questions as fundamental and analytically prior to moral ones: before presenting his theory of what is good and bad, Mill first needs to make a convincing case for how good and bad should be decided. While most fields of thought begin with data and then derive principles from them, philosophy—like mathematics—begins with principles, creates a “general theory” out of them, and then applies this theory to “particular truths.” The first principles of mathematics are straightforward. But those of philosophy are far more difficult, since unlike the basic rules of numbers, they are not obvious to everyone. According to Mill, these first principles of philosophy specifically must come from reason, rather than instinct (although he leaves open the question about whether they come from purely abstract reason, or reasoning about experience). At the very beginning of his introduction, Mill recognizes this set of difficulties and attributes 2,000 years of disagreement among philosophers to it. He believes that they are looking too hard, and in the wrong places, for the foundation of ethical philosophy. The principles they come up with, which they believe to be first principles, are actually derivative second principles. In many cases, this is because they derive these principles from their moral instincts—which Mill thinks almost always agree with moral truths but are ultimately only second-order ways of getting there. For Mill, this problem—the confusion of first and second principles—applies not only to arcane academic philosophy, but also to “morals [and] legislation” (including government), which also require deriving rules from abstract, theoretical truths. If philosophers’ disagreements are largely about their meta-ethical failures, then politicians’ failures probably stem from the same issue. In other words, Mill thinks he can kill two birds with one stone, revolutionizing both ethics and politics simply by investigating where good and evil originate.

From a purely philosophical perspective, utilitarianism’s key innovation is its meta-ethics: Mill believes that he proves its moral principles in a different way than other theories prove theirs, and that this method reveals those other theories’ weaknesses. Utilitarianism presents the principle of maximizing happiness as its one and only first principle and sees all other ethical principles as second-degree corollaries or consequences of this. One argument for this conception is that any other imaginable moral principles will eventually, at some point, conflict—and the only way to decide between them is to choose the principle that, in that case, upholds the greater good. As a result, Mill shows that utilitarianism’s first principle is more fundamental than what other philosophies consider first principles. In the fourth chapter, when it comes to proving his central principle, Mill returns to the idea that there are two basic sources of knowledge that can be used to establish first principles: “our senses and our internal consciousness.” (While he believes ethics should come from the latter, reason, he thinks it is also possible to prove utilitarianism’s validity by reference to the former, instinct.) Mill determines that showing that happiness is the most important end, or desired goal, of action simply means proving that everyone does desire happiness (and nothing but it). He compares it to how “the only proof that a sound is audible is that people hear it”—he believes there is no other way of proving such claims, which are not based on any other more basic claims. It simply is the case that people want to be happy, and it is impossible to make sense of human behavior if one chooses to deny this fact. Mill notes in this chapter that he also has to prove that nothing else is inherently desirable like happiness. He makes a case for this claim by suggesting that happiness is a composite, which can be made of different parts in different contexts—but whenever anyone wants something, they want it either as a means to happiness, or because it is a part of happiness itself. Mill continues that, becuase “each person […] desires [their] own happiness,” therefore “the general happiness” is the prime value for ethics because it is “a good to the aggregate of all persons.” If ethics is supposed to direct people to behave in ways that are objectively or absolutely good, this means people should do what is good from the most objective or impartial perspective—which, for Mill, is that of “the aggregate of all persons.” Good and evil depend on the situation, not the doer.

Although Mill’s supposed proof of utilitarianism seems almost too simple to warrant serious consideration, its simplicity actually makes an important statement about the kind of claims that need to ground ethical thought. While most philosophers worry that it would look stupid or uncreative to make such a straightforward argument and therefore go to great lengths to invent moral principles and elaborate justifications for them, Mill thinks that it is far more honest and important for them to name their principal assumption—that happiness is good, the assumption on which all ethics must rest, and the principle at the center of utilitarianism—and then consciously base the rest of their doctrines on it.

Related Themes from Other Texts
Compare and contrast themes from other texts to this theme…

Meta-Ethics ThemeTracker

The ThemeTracker below shows where, and to what degree, the theme of Meta-Ethics appears in each chapter of Utilitarianism. Click or tap on any chapter to read its Summary & Analysis.
How often theme appears:
chapter length:
Get the entire Utilitarianism LitChart as a printable PDF.
Utilitarianism PDF

Meta-Ethics Quotes in Utilitarianism

Below you will find the important quotes in Utilitarianism related to the theme of Meta-Ethics.
Chapter 1 Quotes

It is not my purpose to criticize these thinkers; but I cannot help referring, for illustration, to a systematic treatise by one of the most illustrious of them, the Metaphysics of Ethics by Kant. This remarkable man, whose system of thought will long remain one of the landmarks in the history of philosophical speculation, does, in the treatise in question, lay down a universal first principle as the origin and ground of moral obligation; it is this: “So act that the rule on which thou actest would admit of being adopted as a law by all rational beings.” But when he begins to deduce from this precept any of the actual duties of morality, he fails, almost grotesquely, to show that there would be any contradiction, any logical (not to say physical) impossibility, in the adoption by all rational beings of the most outrageously immoral rules of conduct. All he shows is that the consequences of their universal adoption would be such as no one would choose to incur.

Related Characters: John Stuart Mill (speaker), Immanuel Kant (speaker)
Page Number: 3-4
Explanation and Analysis:

Questions of ultimate ends are not amenable to direct proof. Whatever can be proved to be good must be so by being shown to be a means to something admitted to be good without proof. The medical art is proved to be good by its conducing to health; but how is it possible to prove that health is good? The art of music is good, for the reason, among others, that it produces pleasure; but what proof is it possible to give that pleasure is good? If, then, it is asserted that there is a comprehensive formula, including all things which are in themselves good, and that whatever else is good is not so as an end but as a means, the formula may be accepted or rejected, but is not a subject of what is commonly understood by proof. We are not, however, to infer that its acceptance or rejection must depend on blind impulse or arbitrary choice. There is a larger meaning of the word “proof,” in which this question is as amenable to it as any other of the disputed questions of philosophy.

Related Characters: John Stuart Mill (speaker)
Related Literary Devices:
Page Number: 4
Explanation and Analysis:
Chapter 3 Quotes

The internal sanction of duty, whatever our standard of duty may be, is one and the same—a feeling in our own mind; a pain, more or less intense, attendant on violation of duty, which in properly cultivated moral natures rises, in the more serious cases, into shrinking from it as an impossibility. This feeling, when disinterested and connecting itself with the pure idea of duty, and not with some particular form of it, or with any of the merely accessory circumstances, is the essence of conscience.

Related Characters: John Stuart Mill (speaker)
Page Number: 28-9
Explanation and Analysis:
Chapter 4 Quotes

The only proof capable of being given that an object is visible is that people actually see it. The only proof that a sound is audible is that people hear it; and so of the other sources of our experience. In like manner, I apprehend, the sole evidence it is possible to produce that anything is desirable is that people do actually desire it. If the end which the utilitarian doctrine proposes to itself were not, in theory and in practice, acknowledged to be an end, nothing could ever convince any person that it was so. No reason can be given why the general happiness is desirable, except that each person, so far as he believes it to be attainable, desires his own happiness. This, however, being a fact, we have not only all the proof which the case admits of, but all which it is possible to require, that happiness is a good: that each person’s happiness is a good to that person, and the general happiness, therefore, a good to the aggregate of all persons.

Related Characters: John Stuart Mill (speaker)
Page Number: 35-6
Explanation and Analysis:

Happiness is not an abstract idea but a concrete whole; and these are some of its parts.

Related Characters: John Stuart Mill (speaker)
Related Symbols: Money
Page Number: 37-8
Explanation and Analysis:
Chapter 5 Quotes

In all ages of speculation one of the strongest obstacles to the reception of the doctrine that utility or happiness is the criterion of right and wrong has been drawn from the idea of justice.

Related Characters: John Stuart Mill (speaker)
Page Number: 42
Explanation and Analysis: