In 1689, English philosopher John Locke anonymously published his political work Two Treatises of Government. Broken into two separate essays, Two Treatises argues the illegitimate nature of patriarchalism—the belief in the absolute power of the monarchy—and offers other approaches for a civilized society. In the Second Treatise of Government, Locke begins his argument with the state of nature, or the way of life of humankind prior to the advent of civil society. The problem, Locke admits, is that historical records of the state of nature don’t exist, so knowing exactly what that state was is impossible. Debates concerning the state of nature were a hot topic in Locke’s day, and Locke specifically refers to Leviathan, a 1651 book published by English philosopher Thomas Hobbes, which famously contends that humankind existing in a state of nature outside of civilized society is “nasty, brutish, and short.” Locke refutes Hobbes’s rather bleak assessment of the state of nature and instead contends that nature is not completely chaotic and lawless; however, whether the law of nature is followed is another matter, and because of this, nature is a very dangerous place. While Locke maintains that the state of nature is “perfect freedom,” he effectively argues through the Second Treatise of Government that a state of nature inevitably leads to a state of war—which Locke defines as a state of “enmity and destruction”—and the creation of civil society. This civil society, he posits, is the only way to curb the “force” of the state of war and protect the law of God which imbues everyone with a fundamental right to life, liberty, and property.
According to Locke, humanity in a state of nature is in a “state of perfect freedom” and absolute liberty, which cannot be infringed upon by another and must be respected by all. Locke argues that in a natural state, every individual has the right “to order their actions, and dispose of their possessions and persons, as they think fit, within the bounds of the law of nature, without asking leave, or depending upon the will of any other man.” In nature, every person has the absolute right to do as they wish upon their own body and belongings, without any kind of outside oversight. Locke also contends that there is perfect equality in nature, where “all the power and jurisdiction is reciprocal, no one having more than another; there being nothing more evident, than that creatures of the same species and rank, promiscuously born to all the same advantages of nature.” In a state of nature, there is equal power and standing among all humankind. This equality, Locke maintains, leads to an added obligation in nature, and he quotes Sir Richard Hooker, a 16th-century English priest, to make his point. According to Locke, Hooker claims all people are obligated to “mutual love amongst men, on which he builds the duties they owe one another, and from whence he derives the great maxims of justice and charity.” The key for Locke’s theory of the state of nature is that each person must recognize and respect this liberty and equality, both in themselves and in other people.
However, despite the “state of perfect freedom” within nature, Locke argues that a civil society is inevitable and necessary—certain laws and rules must be maintained to keep order and civility, and to preserve and protect humankind. A “state of liberty” is not a “state of licence,” Locke argues. In other words, no one can simply do whatever they want. Just because one is free does not mean they are free to act however they please. While one has complete liberty concerning their body and possessions, “he has not liberty to destroy himself, or so much as any creature in his possession.” Plainly put, no one has the right to harm oneself or others, which Locke refers to as the law of nature. This unwritten law maintains that “no one ought to harm another in his life, health, liberty, or possessions.” For Locke, one’s physical possessions are seen as an extension of the body, and thus they cannot be infringed upon by another, either. Locke claims that each individual is “bound to preserve himself,” and he is likewise bound to “preserve the rest of mankind.” The only instance in which one is allowed to harm another person is “to do justice on an offender,” as “every one has a right to punish the transgressors of that law to such a degree, as may hinder its violation.” Simply put, if one’s person or property is harmed by another, they have the absolute right to punish said offender in any way they see fit, up to and including death.
Locke ultimately argues that one has the right to destroy any person who seeks to harm one’s own person or property, which effectively places humans in a state of war with one another. As the state of nature is not ruled by one common power, there is no one to appeal to for help or relief, and the state of war continues, unchecked and unregulated. Locke refers to this state of war as “force,” and he argues it has driven humanity to form civil societies, in an effort to preserve and protect one’s life, liberty, and property.
Nature, War, and Civil Society ThemeTracker
Nature, War, and Civil Society Quotes in Second Treatise of Government
But though this be a state of liberty, yet it is not a state of licence: though man in that state have an uncontrollable liberty to dispose of his person or possessions, yet he has not liberty to destroy himself, or so much as any creature in his possession, but where some nobler use than its bare preservation calls for it. The state of nature has a law of nature to govern it, which obliges every one; and reason, which is that law, teaches all mankind, who will but consult it, that being all equal and independent, no one ought to harm another in his life, health, liberty, or possessions: for men being all the workmanship of one omnipotent, and infinitely wise maker […].
And that all men may be restrained from invading others rights, and from doing hurt to one another, and the law of nature be observed, which willeth the peace and preservation of all mankind, the execution of the law of nature is, in that state, put into every man's hands, whereby every one has a right to punish the transgressors of that law to such a degree, as may hinder its violation […].
I doubt not but it will be objected, that it is unreasonable for men to be judges in their own cases, that self-love will make men partial to themselves and their friends: and on the other side, that ill nature, passion and revenge will carry them too far in punishing others; and hence nothing but confusion and disorder will follow, and that therefore God hath certainly appointed government to restrain the partiality and violence of men. I easily grant, that civil government is the proper remedy for the inconveniencies of the state of nature, which must certainly be great, where men may be judges in their own case, since it is easy to be imagined, that he who was so unjust as to do his brother an injury, will scarce be so just as to condemn himself for it.
And here we have the plain difference between the state of nature and the state of war, which however some men have confounded, are as far distant, as a state of peace, good will, mutual assistance and preservation, and a state of enmity, malice, violence and mutual destruction, are one from another. Men living together according to reason, without a common superior on earth, with authority to judge between them, is properly the state of nature.
This freedom from absolute, arbitrary power, is so necessary to, and closely joined with a man's preservation, that he cannot part with it, but by what forfeits his preservation and life together: for a man, not having the power of his own life, cannot, by compact, or his own consent, enslave himself to any one, nor put himself under the absolute, arbitrary power of another, to take away his life, when he pleases. No body can give more power than he has himself; and he that cannot take away his own life, cannot give another power over it.
Though the earth, and all inferior creatures, be common to all men, yet every man has a property in his own person: this no body has any right to but himself. The labour of his body, and the work of his hands, we may say, are properly his. Whatsoever then he removes out of the state that nature hath provided, and left it in, he hath mixed his labour with, and joined to it something that is his own, and thereby makes it his property. It being by him removed from the common state nature hath placed it in, it hath by this labour something annexed to it, that excludes the common right of other men: for this labour being the unquestionable property of the labourer, no man but he can have a right to what that is once joined to, at least where there is enough, and as good, left in common for others.
And this puts men out of a state of nature into that of a common-wealth, by setting up a judge on earth, with authority to determine all the controversies, and redress the injuries that may happen to any member of the commonwealth; which judge is the legislative, or magistrates appointed by it. And where-ever there are any number of men, however associated, that have no such decisive power to appeal to, there they are still in the state of nature.
No man in civil society can be exempted from the laws of it: for if any man may do what he thinks fit, and there be no appeal on earth, for redress or security against any harm he shall do; I ask, whether he be not perfectly still in the state of nature, and so can be no part or member of that civil society; unless any one will say, the state of nature and civil society are one and the same thing, which I have never yet found any one so great a patron of anarchy as to affirm.
But though men, when they enter into society, give up the equality, liberty, and executive power they had in the state of nature, into the hands of the society, to be so far disposed of by the legislative, as the good of the society shall require; yet it being only with an intention in every one the better to preserve himself, his liberty and property; (for no rational creature can be supposed to change his condition with an intention to be worse) the power of the society, or legislative constituted by them, can never be supposed to extend farther, than the common good; but is obliged to secure every one's property, by providing against those three defects above mentioned, that made the state of nature so unsafe and uneasy.
But in governments, where the legislative is in one lasting assembly always in being, or in one man, as in absolute monarchies, there is danger still, that they will think themselves to have a distinct interest from the rest of the community; and so will be apt to increase their own riches and power, by taking what they think fit from the people: for a man's property is not at all secure, tho' there be good and equitable laws to set the bounds of it between him and his fellow subjects, if he who commands those subjects have power to take from any private man, what part he pleases of his property, and use and dispose of it as he thinks good.
That the aggressor, who puts himself into the state of war with another, and unjustly invades another man's right, can, by such an unjust war, never come to have a right over the conquered, will be easily agreed by all men, who will not think, that robbers and pyrates have a right of empire over whomsoever they have force enough to master; or that men are bound by promises, which unlawful force extorts from them.
He that will with any clearness speak of the dissolution of government, ought in the first place to distinguish between the dissolution of the society and the dissolution of the government. That which makes the community, and brings men out of the loose state of nature, into one politic society, is the agreement which every one has with the rest to incorporate, and act as one body, and so be one distinct common-wealth. The usual, and almost only way whereby this union is dissolved, is the inroad of foreign force making a conquest upon them: for in that case, (not being able to maintain and support themselves, as one intire and independent body) the union belonging to that body which consisted therein, must necessarily cease, and so every one return to the state he was in before, with a liberty to shift for himself, and provide for his own safety, as he thinks fit, in some other society. Whenever the society is dissolved, it is certain the government of that society cannot remain.
To conclude, the power that every individual gave the society, when he entered into it, can never revert to the individuals again, as long as the society lasts, but will always remain in the community; because without this there can be no community, no common-wealth, which is contrary to the original agreement; so also when the society hath placed the legislative in any assembly of men, to continue in them and their successors, with direction and authority for providing such successors, the legislative can never revert to the people whilst that government lasts; because having provided a legislative with power to continue for ever, they have given up their political power to the legislative, and cannot resume it.